The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 126(2), 805–855.
The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 126(2), 805–855.
Research interests
Industrial Organization, Regulation, Organization Theory, Game Theory, Finance, Macroeconomics, Psychology
Research interests
inequality, growth, social mobility and the political economy of redistribution; education, social interactions and the socioeconomic structure of cities; economics and psychology ("behavioral economics")
This paper provides a extremely flexible and feasible model to explain experimental results from Behavioral Economics and Psychology.
Strength of the model but…
Positive Side:
People have strong preference for being a good person.
Negative Side:
People prefer to act selfishly to gain extra money while "feeling moral".
Social Punishments
Antisocial Punishments
A are “relational assets” and the individual’s long-run utility
v is person’s type "good or not"
at is investment decision. (= 1 invest in A, and = 0 not)
rt: the multiplier of moral decision
At+1=At+αtrt to measure the relative increase from choosing at=1
the agent has access to a signal about his type(good or bad)
v={vHvL with probability ρ with probability 1−ρ
prior expectation:
vˉ≡ρvH+(1−ρ)vL
Assumption 1
The net cost of investment at date 0 is c0H≷0 for type H and c0L for type L, with c0L≥c0H
Because a more prosocial individual internalizes more of the benefits accruing to other people, even in one-shot interactions, he finds it (weakly) less costly to act morally—help, refrain from opportunism
Assumption 2. (Self-inference)
the individual is aware of his true valuation v only with probability λ, so with (1−λ), he cannot remember and infer his type based on former choice a0
denote ρ^ as date-1 belief about his type
v^≡ρ^vH+(1−ρ^)vL
so with probability λ, v^ is v; and with 1−λ, v^=v^(a0)∈[vL,vH]
Note:
(1−λ) is malleability of beliefs, the probability of information loss thus also reflecting the possibility that deeds may themselves be forgotten or repressed, or be uninformative due to situational factors that can be invoked as plausible excuses
Assumption 3
The value function V=V(v,v^,A1) satisfies Vv^>0, Vv^v≥0 and, if r0>0, VvA1>0.
Vv^>0: a “good identity” convention, a moral self-image is better than not
Vv^v≥0: a sorting condition, when c0H≤c0L , the investment of H type ≥ the investment of L type (behaving more prosocially), so that actions have informational content(type can be identified from the action)
Assumption 4. Exclude the Trivial Case
we do not want: the investment cost is too low so that both types always invest regardless of identity concerns
we assume:
V(vL,v^=vL,A0+a0r0)−V(vL,v^=vL,A0)<c0L
vA2 is long-term value
reminder of our timing:
Decision only happens at Date-0
a1≡0,A2=A1
What is AU: hopefulness, anxiety, or dread that arise from contemplating future and social prospects
Long-term Utility
vA2, the expected value of social relationships(family, friends, colleagues, ethnic group, etc.)
Intertemporary utility function
V(v,v^,A1)=sv^A1+δvA2
s: anticipatory feelings or salience
δ: the time discount factor
SE is AU when At≡1,rt≡0 and δ=0, so
V(v,v^,A1)=sv^A1+δvA1=sv^
total intertemporal utility
W≡E[−a0c0+V]
depends on:
Present bias
At date 1, a myopic person’ perceived cost of acting morally is c/β(β<vL/vH)
so β exaggerate present cost c
Investment decision a0 happens when t=0,1
Moral Identity and Self-Restraint
given a self-view v^, the agent invests when c1/β≤δv^r1, so threshold cost increases with v^
Total Intertemporal Utility
V(v,v^,A1)≡δvA1+∫0βδv^r1(δvr1−c1)dF(c1)
δvA1: default long-run utility
(δvr1−c1): extra utility from investment choice
Welfare Analysis
W=E[−βa0c0+V]
β is reversed present bias from Date-0
Expected Value Function
V(v,v^,A1)≡λV(v,v,A1)+(1−λ)V(v,v^,A1)
Each type chooses his optimal option a0, k=H,L
a0∈{0,1}max{−c0ka0+λV(vk,vk,A0+a0r0)+(1−λ)V(vk,v^(a0),A0+a0r0)}
Utility depends on v^(a0) and a0
v^(a0)≡ρ^(a0)vH+[1−ρ^(a0)]vL
where ρ^ relates to ρ,xK
ρ^(1)=ρxH+(1−ρ)xLρxH , ρ^(0)=ρ(1−xH)+(1−ρ)(1−xL)ρ(1−xH)
xH and xL: probabilities that types H and L behave prosocially at t=0
Investment choice (a0=1) is optimal when:
V(vk,v^(1),A0+r0)−V(vk,v^(0),A0)−c0k≥0,k=H,L
Monotonic Perfect Bayesian Equilibria (Proposition 1.)
ρ = initial self-image inference
When initial self-image is good enough, the H type can afford not to invest, since the other one also behaves opportunistically the posterior will equal the prior, which is already close to 1 and thus could not be increased much anyway
H invest to “stand for his principles” and separate from the L type
Separation.
When c0L is high, the low-valuation type does not find it worthwhile to invest (xL=0)
Randomization.
For lower values of c0L, L type intend to imitate H type (but ability of imitation is limited by the prior)
Universal Investment.
For c0L still lower, even a small gain in self-image is worth pursuing, so xL=1.
Let’s examine the no-investment condition:
V(vH,vH,A0+r0)−V(vH,vˉ,A0)=(s+δ)vHr0+(1−λ)s(vH−vˉ)A0≤c0H
Notice that when A gets sufficiently large, the agent unavoidably chooses to invest, thus reducing his/her lifetime utility.
More broadly speaking (easy to see when r0≈0):
W=ρxH[(s+δ)vHr0−c0H]+(1−ρ)xL[(s+δ)vLr0−c0L]+(s+δ)vˉA0.
The first two terms decrease as identity investment rises.This leads to more interesting findings.
In Anticipatory Utility case:
reminder: when r0 is relatively small, the underlined items are negative
W=ρxH[(s+δ)vHr0−c0H]+(1−ρ)xL[(s+δ)vLr0−c0L]+(s+δ)vˉA0.
let assume two cases:
(a) λ=1, neither type behaves prosocially at t = 0 : c0H>δvHr0, so xH=xL=0
(b) λ<1, the equilibrium involves mixing: H type cooperates, while L type randomizes.
Difference in intertemporal welfare:
ΔW=W(b)−W(a)=(1−ρ)xL(δvLr0−βc0L)+ρ(δvHr0−βc0H)+(1−λ)E[ΔV]
where E[ΔV] reflects the effects of self-image management on date-1 behavior:
E[ΔV]=(1−ρ)xL∫βδvLr1βδv^(1)r1(δvLr1−c1)dF(c1)−ρ∫βδv^(1)r1βδvHr1(δvHr1−c1)dF(c1)
Proposition 4.
In the self-control case, more malleable beliefs (λ↓) can raise welfare, by improving choices at t=1 (when E[ΔV]>0) and/or at t=0 when ΔW>(1−λ)E[ΔV])
Setting:
type(v)
Let v∈vH,vL denote the long-run value of some important asset, relative to At
Taboo breaking = Selling decision of Assets
Suppose date=0, an agent can find a price p and sell one unit of A0
price distribution is:
p={pH with probability zpL with probability 1-z
Investment choice (a0)
choice={a0=0,check the price + consider selling A0a0=1,keep the taboo, think it priceless
💡 contemplation is done once check
the agent will recall that he contemplated the possibility of a transaction and evaluated whether maintaining his identity or dignity was “worth it”
Selling decision depends on price found
let pH be high enough and pL low enough → transact or not is a signal of type
when p=pH: always sell A0, implies: when p=pL: no transaction, implies:
pH>V(vH,vH,A0)−V(vH,vL,A0−1)pL<V(vL,vH,A0)−V(vL,vL,A0−1)
V(a0=1)−V(a0=0)=V(v,v^(1),A0)−V(v,v^(0),A0−z)≥zpH+(1−z)pL≈zpH
A special case of former modelwhere a0r0=z,c0=zpH and initial stock A0′≡A0−z
Note.
V(v,v^(0),A0−z) can be written because V is linear in A1 in AU and SC case
How taboos arise and are sustained
from proposition 1 and 2, it depends on the initial beliefs ρ
Taboo’s Reaffirmation or Collapse
according to which side of the “hill” the induced erosion of ρ occurs on
on the right side
ρ decrease → reaffirmation
on the left side
ρ decrease → collapse
Welfare effect of taboos
Note.
Proposition 3. An increase in (per se valuable) capital A0 can make the individual worse off.
Focus: coexistence of social and antisocial punishments
r0k=ξvk,c~0H≥c~0L
ξ=1 when the action benefit others and ξ≤0 when notcontinue relationship or not: two agents after observing each other’s action, decide whether to continue in the relationship (yi=0) or to break it (yi=1)
interactions benefit: if someone exit, both lose b
(viξ−c0i)a0i+V(vi,vi,A0+r0a0i)+(1−ν)(1−y)b
ostracism happens condition: y≡1−(1−yi)(1−yj)
Date 1: (no-recall assumptions) each agent always remains aware of his own behavior ai0, but he recalls that of his partner only if they are still together. If a split occurred, he recalls neither a0j nor what caused the separation (extreme and meant only to simplify the derivations)
1. Benchmarking on the Person
two types are the same v1=v2∈{vH,vL}
a0 is always socially useful (ξ≡1)
2. Benchmarking on the Situation
two types are independent
Whether a0 is socially useful is random: ξ=1, with probability θ or ξ≤0, with 1−θ
When faced with a given situation agents are able to assess ξ, but later on they recall imperfectly with probability 1−λ.
In an equilibrium such that the H type invests when (ξ=1), let x∈[0,1] denote the probability of investment by the L type.
Ostracism occurs only when actions differ, i.e. one agent invests and the other not.
Co-existence of Social punishment and Anti-social punishment
benchmarking is on the person = Social punishment
ostracism comes from the good agent
benchmarking is on the situation = Anti-social punishment
ostracism comes from the bad agent
When benchmarking is on the person
x = 1 is sustained by the ostracism of “sinners” (a prosocial norm)
x = 0 involves no ostracism
When benchmarking is on the situation
x = 0 is sustained by the ostracism of “do-gooders” (an antisocial norm)
x = 1 involves no ostracism
shows cross-society-differences in civic norms and how they are enforced
Other Dimensions of Identity
Messages or cues that make specific components of a person’s identity more salient elicit investments along the same dimensions.
Application of salience is advertising, much of which plays up people’s desires to achieve or affirm certain identities—raising s with respect to beauty, wealth, or social status. Proposition 3 shows that such messages can be very effective in inducing consumers to purchase ( a0=1) and yet substantially lower overall welfare.
Proposition 3. In the anticipatory utility or self-image case:
People are insecure about “who they are” (ρ in the middle range) are the most prone to costly identity-affirming behaviors. E.g. adolescents; male subjects with strongly declared homophobia actually showed the most arousal in response to male homoerotic videos.
someone who has built up enough of some economic or social asset—wealth, career, family, culture, etc.—continues to invest in it even when the marginal return no longer justifies it. This leads to excessive specialization (e.g., work versus family) and persistence in unproductive tasks
e.g. A manager will thus keep throwing good money after bad on a doomed project
Social Signaling. In addition to their self-image v^, people also care about others’ perceptions v^′ of their type, resulting in a continuation value of the form V(v,v^,A1,v^′) Since others make inferences from observed behavior, adding a social signaling concern is akin to amplifying the self-image motive, so the entire analysis carries over (see again Appendix II).
The expected value function playing the role of Equation (11) is now
V(v,v^,A1)≡λV(v,v,A1,v^′)+(1−λ)V(v,v^,A1,v^′)
Thus, as long as
(v,v^,A1)⟼V(v,v^,A1,v^′)
satisfies Assumption 3, adding a social signaling concern is akin to amplifying the self-signaling motive (from
(1−λ)V2to(1−λ)V2+V4
and the whole analysis, positive and normative, carries over.
Tradeoff between the future benefits from two identities, investing in one (say, B) inevitably damages the other (A), as it suggests that the individual may not value it that much.
The transition, which is risky and requires new skills and lifestyles, will be resisted if it is seen as de-valuing the old (rural, extended-family, blue-collar, etc.) identity
Immigrants and their descendents experience strong tensions between integrating into Western societies and preserving their specific culture.
Not investing in B in order to safeguard beliefs about the value of A can also mean actively destroying productive B capital. E.g young rioters attacked and destroyed a number of schools, nursery schools and cars in their own communities.
V=(v^+sδv)A,
Answer. When a person is low in self-esteem, they will not gain not much utility from a higher type, which reveals that s is low. As a result, a low-esteem person will lay more emphasis on self-inferred utitlity, so they may do some extreme or srtange things to strengthen their identity pereption.
Answer. Actually, we have experimental evidence shows that deceptive behavior significantly decreases with age (Glätzle-Rützler & Lergetporer, 2015), and another paper studying on the same relationship not got the significant results, but their adopted experimental paradigm may not ensure the credibility of individual-level data (Bucciol & Piovesan, 2011).
Aging changes people’s enjoyment from social capital - gaining a bossom friend at your twentieth is different from knowing awesome friend when you are at the end of your life.